João Labareda
Search for other papers by João Labareda in
Current site
Google Scholar
PubMed
Close
What is the common good?

This chapter develops a conceptual framework to analyse the problem of the common good in a morally and culturally diverse European Union (EU). The author claims that public values – understood as the values endorsed by the fundamental laws of a polity, such as constitutions and international treaties – provide guidance regarding what fundamental conditions and goals a society considers desirable. All citizens of a given polity are expected to uphold its public values, regardless of their individual preferences and worldviews. By bridging the substantial moral differences amongst citizens, public values create a common standpoint against which both individual conduct and public policies ought to be assessed. It is argued that this critical role of public values does not apply exclusively within the nation-state. When the public values endorsed by a given group of states overlap significantly or when they explicitly endorse common values through international agreements (as in the EU), it is plausible to speak of transnational conceptions of the common good. The author suggests that shared understandings of the common good within groups of states will be thicker or thinner depending on the extent to which their public values overlap. He argues that even highly diverse political communities can usually reach a basic level of moral agreement when it comes to addressing certain fundamental global challenges, including climate change and HIV/AIDS, warranting talk of a global common good.

Introduction

This chapter develops a conceptual framework to analyse the problem of the common good in a morally and culturally diverse European Union (EU). It addresses the following questions: What is the common good? On what philosophical grounds, if any, can a diverse group of states, such as Denmark, Italy and Poland, speak of their common good? What are public values? Can public values translate a shared conception of the common good in a diverse polity? I claim that public values – understood as the values endorsed by the fundamental laws of a polity, such as constitutions and international treaties – provide guidance regarding what fundamental conditions and goals a society considers desirable. All citizens of a given polity are expected to uphold its public values, regardless of their individual preferences and worldviews. By bridging the substantial moral differences amongst citizens, public values create a common standpoint against which both individual conduct and public policies ought to be assessed. I argue that this critical role of public values does not apply exclusively within the nation-state. When the public values endorsed by a given group of states overlap significantly or when they explicitly endorse common values through international agreements (as in the EU), it is plausible to speak of transnational conceptions of the common good. I suggest that shared understandings of the common good within groups of states will be thicker or thinner depending on the extent to which their public values overlap. Regarding the relations between polities with clashing conceptions of the common good, such as the United States and Iran, I claim that states should, in principle, respect each other’s conception, provided that they do not perform gross and systemic violations of the fundamental rights enshrined in international law. However, I argue that even highly diverse political communities can usually reach a basic level of moral agreement when it comes to addressing certain fundamental global challenges, including climate change and HIV/AIDS, warranting talk of a global common good.

I begin by defining the concept of the common good and situating it within the landscape of contemporary political theory. I also identify a few key challenges to which the common good has recently been exposed. Then, I introduce the notion of public values and discuss their main features. Subsequently, I investigate whether and to what extent public values may apply beyond the nation-state. I discuss two moral principles to guide the relations between states and regions that have clashing conceptions of the common good. Furthermore, I present a few trade-offs linked to the transnational pursuit of the common good that may imply sacrificing some national interests. Finally, I briefly outline a strategy to advance the common good beyond borders.

The common good: a conceptual framework

The common good: still a useful concept?

Since the concept of the common good is simultaneously “self-evident and confused”, it pays to begin with a definition.1 By common good, I mean the conditions and goals that benefit a community as a whole without imposing impermissible harm on some of its members. This definition emphasises two critical aspects. To begin with, the common good refers to conditions and goals that benefit a political community at large, as opposed to limited groups of individuals. While, as we shall see, pursuing the common good does not always mean improving the well-being of all citizens, policies for the common good are expected to generate benefits for at least the large majority of them and provide a compelling justification for the sacrifices they may require from the remaining groups.2 Note that, as has rightly been argued, these widespread benefits cannot always be captured by means of summing individual utilities in a narrow utilitarian fashion.3 For example, investing in a public school system benefits not only students who attend better-equipped schools but also the broader community by improving literacy levels, enhancing innovation capacity and promoting social mobility. Indeed, these are conditions and goals that most societies consider desirable. Therefore, the notion of the common good is not normatively redundant on a purely aggregative moral doctrine.4

Second, this definition emphasises the point that the common good should not be advanced at any cost.5 As I will claim, the pursuit of the common good provides moral grounds to demand certain sacrifices from some citizens and social groups, but there are limits as to what should be asked on behalf of the greater good. For instance, redistributing wealth and income typically reduces socioeconomic inequalities within a community. Reduced inequality, in turn, improves the physical and mental health of citizens, strengthens the educational performance of children and diminishes the level of violence, thereby contributing to the common good.6 However, if scaled up to a degree in which the marginal utilities of individuals would be equalised, as Peter Singer has famously suggested, redistribution may jeopardise certain fundamental individual rights, notably the right to property.7 Crucially, certain policies that may enhance the common good imply morally unacceptable bodily or psychological harm. Consider, for example, the use of torture to obtain information about the location of the members of a terrorist group. These cases suggest that the common good is not an ultimate goal – that is, it should be weighed against other relevant considerations. Therefore, pursuing the common good is incompatible with imposing morally impermissible harm, which this book shall equate with gross violations of fundamental rights.8

So why does the common good matter at all? As will become apparent, this concept is particularly relevant as a means to provide justification for much-needed yet politically and economically demanding reforms, as well as to contest policy agendas that only serve the interests of small and privileged groups. This point has been forcefully made within the “contractarian” tradition, for whom the primary purpose of creating a network of shared political institutions supported by a monopoly of force is to improve the general welfare – not just that of a few individuals. Relying on the idea of the social contract – either in an explicit, tacit, or hypothetical format – contractarian authors have argued that citizens would only consent to the creation of a coercive state if this would allow collective action problems to be solved and the provision of certain goods that improve everyone’s living standards.9 Accordingly, John Rawls has stated that “[g]‌overnment is assumed to aim at the common good”.10 Yet, as has been widely documented, contemporary policymaking processes are to a large extent shaped by well-organised private interests, which have a disproportional capacity to influence policy outcomes.11 All too often, the agendas of certain political parties, business conglomerates, and religious groups are prioritised over the common good in domains as varied as public health, education and environmental protection. This state of affairs calls for a renewed debate about the pursuit of the common good.12

However, contemporary political theorists have increasingly regarded this concept as problematic. In their view, the following question has become unavoidable: How can there be a common good in highly diverse societies? For authors such as Aristotle and Jean-Jacques Rousseau, moral diversity did not present itself as a major challenge against the pursuit of the common good since the content of public policies would be determined by relatively small city-states and republics where a consensus was usually in reach through effective public deliberation.13 In turn, for a medieval philosopher such as St. Thomas Aquinas, the shared ethical framework provided by a common religion under Christendom would leave no room for fundamental disagreements about the nature of goodness.14 Yet, due to the processes of modernisation and secularisation, societies became more heterogeneous and plural. This development has led to the coexistence of multiple conceptions of goodness, which cannot always be reconciled. Given this change of circumstances, and despite having been a recurrent theme throughout the history of political thought, the common good has been relegated to a secondary role by contemporary political theorists. At present, the so-called communitarian scholars remain its leading proponents, notably Michael Walzer, Charles Taylor and Amitai Etzioni.15

Yet these authors have arguably failed to provide compelling answers as to how the concept of the common good can accommodate the changes wrought by modernisation and secularisation, particularly when it comes to moral and cultural diversity and global interdependence. Indeed, most communitarians still associate the conception of the common good of a given political community with a set of moral beliefs and social and cultural norms widely shared in that community, which they typically take for granted.16 However, this implausibly replicates the assumptions about cultural homogeneity and broad moral consensus underpinning the works of Aristotle and Aquinas, which no longer hold in contemporary societies. Furthermore, unlike what communitarians seem to assume, self-governing communities such as the nation-state currently lack sufficient means to realise the common good.17 In fact, given the high level of interdependence that globalisation has brought about, political communities increasingly need each other to pursue the common good. For example, the goal of addressing climate change, which many nation-states consider desirable, can only be fulfilled through close transnational cooperation. As we shall see, the transnational nature of the common good is particularly apparent in the EU case, for which communitarianism has a blind spot.18 Therefore, a compelling account of the common good for the 21st century will have to accommodate these significant developments.

A few methodological challenges

It is worth noting that the conceptual difficulties underpinning the common good are not only linked to a change in historical circumstances but also to some complex epistemological issues. How can we know, or agree on, what the common good stands for? The so-called epistemic account of democracy advocates “the capacity of ‘the many’ to make correct decisions and seeks to justify democracy by reference to this ability”.19 In its classical formulation, this view presupposes the existence of independent standards of truth against which competing policy options can be assessed.20 Thus, on this account, a key challenge is designing procedures through which the “good” options may be effectively selected.

Yet political communities face at least a degree of epistemic uncertainty under which it may be difficult to foresee which course of action will advance the common good.21 For example, in the face of Russia’s threat to invade Ukraine, Western states had to decide whether to adopt bold preventive measures or explore diplomatic channels without knowing which options would be more effective. In addition, “the many” may clearly make bad decisions.22 Consider, for instance, the victory of the National Socialist Party in the 1933 elections in Germany. Such outcomes have bred “suspicion about the use of independent standards of correctness or truth in the realm of democratic decision making”.23

Alternatively, it may be plausibly argued that the common good is a socially constructed moral standpoint. According to this view, each polity’s understanding of “good” and “bad” collective choices depends on what its citizens have defined as standards of public morality, typically through the mediation of political institutions. Instead of taking the common good as a given, this account equates the latter with explicit moral commitments by a community.24 It thus regards the common good as an “essentially contested concept” in relation to which each community may have more or less plausible conceptions.25 This view is more compelling than the epistemic account, given that it is ready to accommodate the circumstances of moral pluralism and epistemic uncertainty described above.26 However, it does not automatically circumvent the question of how a common standard of goodness can be found in a morally diverse society in the first place. Indeed, given the high level of moral and political polarisation in many present-day polities, the Rawlsian hypothesis of “overlapping consensus” between competing comprehensive doctrines of the good will hardly hold.27 If it is reasonable to assume that “individuals have some degree of interpretive competence or authority in the identification and interpretation of common goods”, then one will need to identify clearly the putative source of a common moral standpoint that guides collective choices.28

Therefore, in order to articulate a conceptual framework of the common good that is suitable for a highly diverse and interdependent EU, we will need to address the following questions: On what philosophical grounds, if any, can a group of states as diverse as Denmark, Italy and Poland speak of their common good? How can we know what specific good(s) are constitutive elements of the conception of the common good of any particular polity, such as the EU? In this chapter, I will claim that these questions can be tackled effectively by analysing the public values endorsed by the political institutions of the communities at stake. I will argue that public values provide a common standpoint to normatively assess public choices, irrespective of the multiplicity of private conceptions of the good. As we shall see, these values are outlined in the fundamental sources of any legal order, notably constitutions and international agreements. Subsequently, in Chapter 2, I will apply this theoretical framework to the EU. I will claim that the question of whether a culturally diverse EU where EU citizens are socially detached could share common standards of public morality has to be addressed in light of the international treaties that its member states have voluntarily entered into with one another. I will show that EU treaties are morally loaded and provide robust grounds for a shared conception of the common good.

Note that this study of the public values of the EU will have to be complemented by a pragmatic discussion concerning the institutional practices by which these values could be realised.29 Indeed, the following question will be in order: What types of institutional rules and procedures could facilitate the pursuit of the conception of the common good enshrined in the EU treaties? While in recent years, several proposals to improve the standards of public deliberation have been put forward by the specialised literature, they do not always offer practicable solutions for a transnational polity with nearly 450 million citizens and 24 official languages.30 Furthermore, a system of multilevel governance, such as the EU, brings about unique challenges that call for tailor-made solutions. Therefore, the question of how to make EU policymaking more oriented towards the common good remains largely unaddressed. As I will argue, the main challenge at the EU level is related to the chronic conflicts of national interests. In a nutshell, even if the member states have agreed, or were to agree, on common values, it may still be hard to mobilise the resources and means to put them into practice. This difficulty is particularly salient given that the institutional architecture of the EU does not comprise a fully-fledged supranational government. I will discuss these issues in detail in Chapters 3 and 4.

What are public values?

Values can be defined as points of reference that provide guidance regarding what is good and bad.31 In what follows, I will focus on a particular category of values that has been scarcely analysed by moral and political theory – namely, public values. Public values are the values endorsed by the political institutions of a polity, notably by explicitly granting them a binding status in the fundamental laws that govern all public policies, state–citizen relations and the relations among citizens.32 Understood in this way, public values are those values enshrined in the political constitutions of states, as well as in sources with equivalent legal status, such as charters and bills of rights and certain international agreements and conventions.33 Examples of familiar public values endorsed by most liberal democracies are the rule of law, solidarity, equality (with its many qualifiers, including social, gender and intergenerational equality) and freedom (namely, of expression, association, the press, and so on). As I will claim below, political communities tend to gradually develop the meaning and implications of their values through policymaking processes, landmark judicial decisions and continuous public debates. This interactive process – which I dub the interpretation of public values – allows societies to translate such values into particular models of social relations and institutional practices.

What is crucial about public values is that they provide a basic degree of normative consensus that allows citizens to assess social arrangements and patterns of behaviour through common moral lenses despite their different moral outlooks.34 In contrast to personal values, public values are not connected to one’s particular worldview, ethical convictions or religious beliefs. They provide normative guidance to all public officials and citizens, regardless of their respective backgrounds and perspectives. In doing so, public values create a common viewpoint from which collective choices can be publicly labelled as “good” or “bad” – the standpoint of the common good.35 It should be emphasised that public values do not consist of an all-encompassing code of conduct.36 As a result, they are compatible with diverse private understandings of the good life. Yet, by the very fact that they have been granted constitutional status, public values have priority over private conceptions of the good. For instance, in a political community that has endorsed the value of equality, individuals are expected to make collective choices on the grounds of an egalitarian standpoint, regardless of their ethical convictions and religious beliefs.37 Admittedly, this expectation presupposes a willingness to compromise for the sake of the community. As I will claim in Chapter 5, this can realistically be achieved in the presence of civic friendship.38

Now, this conceptual framework raises a few questions that deserve close examination. First, what if a polity has endorsed a set of public values that are morally objectionable? Consider, for instance, a constitution that fails to recognise the value of socioeconomic equality, as in the case of the constitution of Chile.39 Should constitutions that arguably encompass an undesirable conception of the common good be disregarded? Second, what can be said about cases where public values are one thing on paper and another in practice? For example, the Chinese constitution asserts the equality of all ethnic groups, but the Chinese authorities reportedly persecute the Uyghur minority.40 What conditions should be fulfilled for a value to be meaningfully endorsed by political institutions? Third, what if the values enshrined in a constitution are not representative of the whole society? Consider, for instance, the 52 (out of 195) world constitutions that fail to sanction gender equality.41 Can the values of these constitutions still be said to express the standpoint of the common good? Fourth, how exactly does the interpretation of public values work in practice? Can it overcome the fact that certain states do not possess a written constitution? Finally, if public values are crystallised in enduring legal sources such as constitutions and international treaties, how do they accommodate the fact that societies undergo moral change? Can public values also change? I will address each of these issues in turn.

I should begin by explaining why, in most cases, this book takes public values at face value – that is, in how they are phrased in constitutions and other equivalent legal sources. Note that my purpose is not to discuss whether the public values of a given polity are normatively desirable but to investigate whether the values of different political communities may overlap and, if so, to what extent. This exercise calls for empirical sources that allow for meaningful comparisons. By relying on constitutions and international agreements, one can test in a systematic manner the existence of transnational conceptions of the common good.42 Admittedly, this methodological approach is exposed to the charge that the values endorsed by certain communities translate objectionable conceptions of the common good.

Yet conducting a normative assessment of the values of each political community also comes with distinct risks. To begin with, unless one adopts some form of moral realism, it is difficult to adjudicate categorically which public values are desirable and which are not.43 Furthermore, a few past attempts to perform similar exercises have simplistically assumed that liberal values are preferable.44 Therefore, while not every public value is normatively sound, referring to each polity’s current inventory of values presents as the most promising strategy.

However, this does not exclude the application of certain basic plausibility criteria. To begin with, it is crucial to ensure a correspondence between the letter of the law and the institutional practices within a political community. Indeed, “[c]‌onstitutions in authoritarian regimes are often denigrated as meaningless exercises in political theatre”.45 For instance, the Portuguese constitution of 1933 enshrined values such as freedom of expression and association that the authoritarian regime of the Portuguese dictator António de Oliveira Salazar scarcely intended to implement.46 This variance suggests that an appropriate threshold for a value to qualify as public value should incorporate a high level of compliance, not merely explicit adoption through a constitutional text.47 Furthermore, public values should be reasonably representative of the citizens that they are meant to bind. Note that, in some polities, the values of a particular social group are brutally imposed on other citizens. Consider, for example, the case of the Sunni rule of Iraq under Saddam Hussein, in which a religious minority shaped the values of the whole community. This systemic discrimination of a group of citizens jeopardises the ability of public values to function as a standpoint that can be plausibly regarded as the common good. As we shall see, this suggests that any plausible conception of the common good presupposes the fulfilment of certain fundamental rights.

Let me now turn to the interpretation of public values. Interpreting public values means deliberating about alternative ways of putting them into practice and making corresponding choices. This specification is crucial because, as I have mentioned, values are only points of reference – that is, they are generic and abstract by definition. To illustrate the point, consider the public value of solidarity. Once a political community has endorsed this value, it must decide how it will be realised. For example, solidarity may be translated into universal access to healthcare, a progressive taxation system or access to unemployment benefits. In turn, the healthcare system may be run by the state or the private sector and offer more or less comprehensive coverage. In the specific context of Western democracies, these choices have led to the development of distinctive models of democracy and social welfare that aim at realising similarly democratic public values.48 It should be added that this process of interpretation takes place through a variety of channels. For instance, at the EU level, the value of solidarity has been interpreted through a wide range of legislation, policy measures, judicial decisions, and public debates.49 Note that this requirement to interpret public values is not a shortcoming. Rather, it ensures they become a widely internalised moral standpoint. Multiple channels of interpretation also exist in states that, despite not having written constitutions, possess functioning “constitutional orders”.50

Finally, it is worth addressing briefly the issue of moral change. The fact that societies undergo moral change, at times leading to what have been dubbed “moral revolutions”, is undeniable.51 A constitutional order is able to accommodate such calls in at least two ways. First, the interpretation of the existing public values by judges, policymakers and citizens may evolve as a result of the resetting of the moral compass of society. For instance, many democracies have legalised same-sex marriage by expanding their interpretation of the values of equality and liberty.52 Second, more radical changes may be institutionalised through effective constitutional amendments or even the redrafting of the constitution. Note that none of these options is merely hypothetical. For example, the Constitution of the United States has been amended 27 times.53 Similarly, in 1958, France – already a consolidated democracy – elected to rewrite its constitution in the face of profound social and moral change.54 It should be added that the public values enshrined in constitutions and international agreements may themselves induce moral change, as during the transition from communism to democracy in several former communist states of Central and Eastern Europe. Therefore, public values allow us to capture a community’s conception of the common good without prejudice of moral change.

Cultural values versus public values

How does this conceptual framework relate to the uses of values in public discourse? In recent years, values have featured increasingly in European politics. President Emmanuel Macron of France went as far as to say that values are “the most precious feature of a nation, which keeps it alive and makes it great”.55 Yet many public officials do not share the understanding of public values presented above. Instead, they refer to what I dub cultural values – that is, points of reference that offer guidance on what is “good” and “bad” based on the social and cultural practices of a specific group. To illustrate the point, consider the EU immigration crisis. In many heated public debates on this matter, the leaders of a few far-right parties conveyed the message that immigrants were undermining “our values”, by which they meant cultural categories of values such as “national values”, “Christian values” and “Western values”. Yet these categories remain underspecified. For example, according to Prime Minister Viktor Orbán, “Hungarian values” can be equated with “Christian values” – even if, as an observer has pointed out, “the policies of Orbán’s government don’t seem to be particularly Christian”.56 This fluidity suggests that cultural values are poorly codified. In what follows, my goal is not to claim that cultural values are meaningless but rather that they do not offer a consistent basis to approach the common good.

Indeed, cultural values have several shortcomings when it comes to establishing a common moral standpoint in a given society. To begin with, the lack of codification that I have alluded to empowers political actors to shape the meaning of cultural values according to their interests and needs. Consider, for example, the terrorist attack against the headquarters of the French satirical magazine Charlie Hebdo in January 2015. In the aftermath of this tragic event, Marine Le Pen of the far-right National Rally contrasted a self-serving understanding of “French values” to those of the Islamic world.57 While French values were said to be strongly attached to a culture of freedom and toleration, Islamic values were linked to violence and fundamentalism. Paradoxically, the Islamophobia that this recurrent type of public discourse helped generate reportedly caused an increase in anti-Muslim acts in France, thereby further challenging the values that the terrorists had targeted in the first place.58 Furthermore, cultural values are not usually subject to scrutiny and are not easily contestable. For instance, in oppressive societies, certain discriminated social groups, such as women and LGBTIQ people, may lack a real chance to challenge dominant worldviews and standard cultural practices. This lack of contestability indicates that the cultural values of a large social group should not be directly labelled as public values.

Understanding public values as the values that the political institutions of a nation-state have explicitly endorsed has several advantages compared to the alternative of defining them as the cultural values of an “imagined community”.59 First, unlike any unwritten set of cultural values, public values are clearly listed in official documents, and their meaning is interpreted by political institutions in formal proceedings. This publicity provides a clear and widely acknowledged basis for a shared understanding of the common good. Second, as I have shown, public values are contestable and can change. Accordingly, in the presence of representative political institutions, public values will likely not be merely equivalent to the values of a dominant ethnic or religious group. Third, rather than taking a cultural identity for granted, which is a problematic assumption in today’s increasingly multicultural societies, public values are the outcome of the social construction of a shared civic identity. This perspective accommodates the fact that in every state, many individuals with different cultural backgrounds abide by the same common moral code.60 In fact, the large majority of the Islamic community of France, which represents 8.8% of the French population, complies with the French public values, regardless of their cultural background and religious beliefs.61 Finally, as the following sections will show, understanding national values as publicly endorsed values allows us to investigate the overlaps and disjunctions between “our values” and “the values of others” in a systematic manner.

This line of reasoning suggests that framing the normative diversity across borders in terms of a “clash of civilisations” offers us scant help in making sense of the moral outlook of the international system.62 Different national communities may uphold diverse values, but this is not necessarily a by-product of their contrasting cultures. If this were the case, how would we explain the common list of public values endorsed by the citizens of Switzerland, a country comprised of French, Italian and German-speaking cantons? In fact, the function of explicit and contestable public values as a common standpoint of goodness is what allows highly diverse states to make sound collective choices. Crucially, this argument can be extrapolated: if it is possible to articulate a common standpoint for the nation-state, despite the diversity within it, then nothing should prevent us from thinking that there could be common standpoints beyond borders. While the degree of institutionalisation of values is admittedly lower beyond the nation-state than within, a rich array of international treaties, agreements and conventions provides grounds for (at least minimalistic) regional and global standpoints of the common good. As we shall see, even countries with very different moral outlooks have worked together to fulfil certain basic requirements of the common good.

The common good at the regional and global levels

Public values beyond borders

In the last decades, an extensive institutional framework has emerged through the signing of international agreements. Many of these voluntary agreements are morally loaded, revealing the fact that a few public values are shared across national borders. For instance, the 191 states that have ratified the Treaty on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons have jointly endorsed the values of peace, security and cooperation.63 Note that this treaty is not just a statement of good intentions; indeed, it is subject to regular reviews that recommend follow-up actions.64 Similarly, the Convention against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment commits its 173 members to the value of human dignity, establishing a common understanding of this value, particularly by setting certain mandatory requirements concerning the treatment of individuals, which are monitored by the Committee against Torture.65 In turn, the 182 states that are part of the International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination endorsed jointly the values of equality and non-discrimination.66 On the grounds of this convention, the Committee on the Elimination of Racial Discrimination has developed a comprehensive jurisprudence on discriminatory practices.67 By joining these conventions, the signatory states have expressed the view that a good world is one without war, torture and racism. In doing so, they have built a shared – even if minimalistic – understanding of goodness.

Yet the overlap of public values on the international stage goes beyond basic moral standards. Indeed, the so-called “like-minded states” often feature remarkably similar moral outlooks.68 For example, liberal democracies such as Norway, Australia and Japan endorse analogous public values, including the rule of law, freedom of speech and accountable government. Even if their interpretation of these values may differ, they clearly share a similar “grammar of the common good”.69 Sharing a range of values allows these countries to assess certain international developments from a similar standpoint. For example, a large group of democratic states have jointly condemned human rights violations in China, Russia’s invasion of Ukraine and the deforestation of the Amazon rainforest. Similarly, communist states such as Laos, Cuba and Venezuela share a constellation of public values denouncing the wrongdoings of capitalism and imperialism. Crucially, many like-minded states have joined international organisations that in themselves presuppose certain common values.70 In fact, some of these organisations have the explicit purpose of advancing a particular set of values. Consider, for instance, the Council of Europe, which aims to promote human rights, democracy and the rule of law.71

This moral convergence is nowhere as visible as in the ongoing processes of regional integration. Regional associations, such as the EU, the Association of Southeast Asian Nations (ASEAN) and the Southern Common Market (Mercosur), are grounded on and governed by voluntary international agreements that generate significant normative commitments for their signatories. Indeed, EU membership is conditional on endorsing the values listed in the EU treaties. Building on Ian Manners’ research, the next chapter will claim that EU values are sustainable peace, social liberty, consensual democracy, associative human rights, supranational rule of law, inclusive equality, social solidarity, sustainable development and good governance.72 In turn, the ASEAN Charter advances, among others, the values of the rule of law, good governance, democracy, the promotion and protection of human rights and the promotion of social justice.73 Along the same lines, Mercosur has enacted protocols regarding the protection and promotion of democracy and human rights, which foresee the possibility of suspending the membership of non-compliant states.74 Accordingly, as I will argue in Chapter 2, it is plausible to speak of “European” values, “Southeast Asian” values and “South American” values if the latter are equated with the values publicly endorsed within the respective regional frameworks.75

This line of argument suggests that it is possible to articulate meaningful conceptions of the common good beyond the nation-state. In the context of the relations between like-minded states, particularly within regional associations, potentially thick shared understandings of the common good may be identified by referring to the values enshrined in the international agreements upon which these organisations are grounded. By applying this strategy, we may speak of the common good of the EU without facing serious charges of conceptual indeterminacy.76

In turn, we can consistently speak of the global common good by referring to the values explicitly endorsed by a large majority of world states.77 Despite the diversity of national conceptions of the common good, significant normative overlaps can be found. I have already mentioned the widespread recognition of goods such as non-proliferation, human dignity and non-discrimination, but many other examples of transnational moral consensus could be added. For instance, most states regard environmental protection as a morally desirable goal. This commitment has allowed them to establish common decarbonisation targets, regardless of their disagreements in other domains. The point that a degree of consensus is possible amongst morally diverse states is powerfully illustrated by the fact that the Paris Climate Agreement brought together countries with contrasting moral outlooks, ranging from Israel and Pakistan to Laos and the Holy See.78

Of course, this cooperation does not obscure the serious moral disagreements on the international stage. For example, when it comes to the value of human life, states have positioned themselves on different sides of the fence. While 90 countries have endorsed the Protocol to the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, which seeks to abolish the death penalty, 110 states have taken no action towards its adoption.79 More generally, the moral outlooks endorsed by certain states are noticeably in tension with each other. Consider, for example, the case of the United States and Iran. The American public values of religious toleration and freedom of speech seem to be at odds with the values of the “sovereignty of truth” and “Qur’anic justice” prescribed by the Constitution of the Islamic Republic of Iran.80 Moreover, these contrasting understandings of the common good have generated serious political tensions. For instance, during the Iranian Revolution, the late Ayatollah Ruhollah Khomeini dubbed the United States “the Great Satan”. Decades later, President George W. Bush famously labelled Iran as part of an “axis of evil”.81 Such examples raise the following questions: How should countries or regions with different conceptions of the common good interact? To what extent do these disagreements jeopardise the pursuit of the common good at the global level? The following sections will address these questions in detail.

Clashing conceptions of the common good

In this section, I will claim that states have a moral duty to respect each other’s conceptions of the common good, provided that the conceptions at stake fulfil a crucial requisite. By respecting a state’s conception of the common good, I mean (i) abstaining from any deliberate attempt to interfere in the domestic affairs of another state with the purpose of changing its public values and (ii) maintaining, to the extent possible, certain basic international conditions that allow the conceptions of the common good of other states to be realised. I shall refer to these two moral claims as the principle of pluralism. However, I will argue that the duty to comply with this principle is contingent on the fulfilment of a critical requirement – that the conception of the common good of a given state does not bring about the infliction of impermissible harm on its citizens or the citizens of other states. For the purpose of this discussion, I understand impermissible harm as a gross and systemic violation of fundamental rights as codified by international law. For example, the Nazi aspiration of creating an ethnically homogeneous and territorially enlarged German community through the suppression of minorities and the conquest of other nations would not be defensible on pluralistic grounds.82 I shall dub this requisite as the principle of respect for fundamental rights. I will discuss these principles in turn.

Let us begin with the principle of pluralism. Why should states respect each other’s conception of the common good? A key reason behind this claim is that a conception of the common good is an important instrument of self-determination. In a broad sense, “self-determination refers to a community’s right to govern itself independently”.83 Respecting self-determination means that there are things that we should not do to sovereign states, “even if for their own ostensible good”.84 By coercively imposing its public values on another political community, a given state would undermine that community’s ability to define autonomously the key goals that it aims to pursue. This does not mean that nothing should be done to promote moral change beyond borders. For example, refraining from “liberal imperialism” does not necessarily imply abstaining from advocating democratic values in the international sphere.85 To be sure, it is plausible to conceive a world “where democracy spreads through dialogue and incentives, not coercion and war”.86 In particular, non-state actors such as NGOs and think tanks are well positioned to take part in non-hierarchical, non-paternalistic “democratic iterations” because they do not hold coercive power against the states where they would like to promote change.87 This suggests that respect for moral diversity is compatible with improving the global moral outlook.88

What, then, does pluralism entail? At first glance, respecting the diversity of the conceptions of the common good presupposes compliance with the familiar norm of non-interference, according to which states should not meddle in each other’s domestic affairs.89 Yet, abiding by the pluralist principle also requires varying degrees of cooperation between countries with conflicting moral outlooks.90 Note that if states refuse to engage with each other on the grounds of their moral disagreements, certain basic conditions for realising the common good in their domestic spheres may not be fulfilled.91 The case of the United States and Cuba is illustrative. Here, two constellations of public values have been in conflict for decades. Given Cuba’s geographical location, the functioning of its institutions is highly dependent on its economic relations with the United States. By embargoing trade with its island neighbour, the US government has significantly constrained Cuba’s ability to realise the level of social welfare underpinning its public values.92 A more extreme case is the current overuse of natural resources, which may ultimately leave little room for any state to pursue its conception of the common good. Hence, in a highly interdependent world, fulfilling the principle of pluralism presupposes the willingness of morally diverse states to work together.

Yet, the imperative of pluralism should be conditional on the fulfilment of certain fundamental rights, understood as the basic and inviolable rights and freedoms codified in international law.93 Why is the observance of these rights so important? As has been widely argued, statehood generates duties for political institutions in their relations towards their citizens.94 Even for a political thinker with authoritarian sympathies, such as Thomas Hobbes, membership in a polity is desirable only if it fosters individuals’ chances of self-preservation.95 These duties suggests that systemic violations of the fundamental rights of citizens are incompatible with any plausible understanding of the common good.96 For example, authorities in countries that conduct arbitrary arrests, torture and the assassination of minorities on a regular basis cannot reasonably defend these practices by referring to a local understanding of the common good. What is at stake in these cases is not moral diversity but mass violence. While the systemic failure to comply with basic standards of decency does not automatically authorise the use of last-resort means such as humanitarian interventions, it may give grounds for the international community to actively seek a change in the status quo.97 Therefore, the principle of pluralism should not apply to what John Rawls has referred to as “outlaw states”.98

This view raises at least two difficult questions: (i) What rights should be regarded as fundamental? (ii) How to set the threshold beyond which fundamental rights violations should no longer be tolerated? Here, I can only provide some general guidelines.99 Regarding the first question, it should be noted that in the last decades, several international treaties and conventions have codified a number of fundamental rights, including the right to life, bodily integrity and due process.100 The question remains as to whether a more extensive list of fundamental rights is needed, one that would include, for instance, social rights and democracy.101 Yet, for the specific purpose of flagging practices that are not worthy of respect under the principle of pluralism, the list of fundamental rights to apply should be relatively parsimonious, or it will risk mirroring the conception of the common good of one particular group of states.102 Regarding the appropriate threshold to apply, the common denominator across different agencies that monitor compliance with fundamental rights is that violations should be gross and systemic.103 These international bodies have developed a comprehensive body of case law concerning what counts as a gross and systemic violation. As the multiple international agreements mentioned above illustrate, there is a robust consensus around the list of fundamental rights currently recognised in international law.

Who should bear the burdens of the common good?

Regardless of how thick the moral agreement between a given group of states is, the pursuit of their common good may bring about intricate disputes about who should bear its burdens.104 On the one hand, there may be grounds to sacrifice the interests of a particular state for the sake of others. To illustrate the point, consider a scarce resource, such as lithium. Assume that the government of Chile – which possesses 55% of the world reserves of this mineral – bans any exports of it to stimulate its national industries.105 This policy would possibly increase the well-being of Chilean citizens by attracting foreign investment and creating better jobs. Yet, it would also likely retard the development and market uptake of green mobility solutions, which are highly dependent on lithium batteries, thus jeopardising the fight against climate change.106 This scenario suggests that Chile is morally required to share its lithium reserves with other states.107 On the other hand, it would seem morally wrong for a given region to seek its common good by means of imposing disproportional sacrifices on a particular state.108 Yet such an outcome clearly obtains when, for instance, Western states promote high environmental standards in their territories by dispatching decommissioned ships to scrapyards in Bangladesh for polluting and hazardous disassembly. This example suggests that the common good of a given state or region should be pursued only to the extent that doing so does not imply inflicting impermissible harm on others.

Yet, what does impermissible harm mean in the context of interstate relations? While discussing this issue in the context of domestic state–citizen relations, I emphasised the moral requirement to respect fundamental rights. Now, if the fundamental rights of citizens are so significant from a normative standpoint, there is no reason to think that those of non-nationals should simply be ignored.109 This point is particularly relevant for our discussion because the behaviour of a given polity may, in certain cases, dramatically condition the fulfilment of fundamental rights in other polities. An illustrative example is armed conflict. By invading Ukraine, Russia seriously breached the fundamental rights of Ukrainian citizens. This reasoning can duly be extended to several other domains. For instance, the current international division of labour, which has largely been shaped by Western states and multinational firms based in them, has consistently led to the violation of workers’ fundamental rights in many developing countries.110 Consequently, some states are at present able to ensure high levels of welfare for their citizens at the expense of the curtailment of fundamental rights elsewhere. Therefore, the limits to the pursuit of the common good of a state or region can be plausibly formulated in the following way: the common good of a given state or region should only be pursued to the extent that it does not imply gross and systemic violations of fundamental rights of the citizens of other states or regions.

A question that follows is how the trade-offs between the common good of different communities could be adjudicated while ensuring high standards of protection of fundamental rights across borders. As we shall see in the following chapters, the EU case offers a promising way forward. Realising the common good of the whole EU often requires sacrificing the interests of a particular member state. For example, ensuring the sustainability of the public finances of most member states required the Irish government to abandon its policy of tax heavens for digital companies, from which the Irish economy has benefited greatly. By the same token, any serious improvement in the working conditions in poor world regions may imply lower profit margins for EU companies and a potentially lower level of economic growth in the common market. Note that the EU possesses a comprehensive institutional framework where these and other trade-offs can be debated democratically, and compromises can be negotiated. Indeed, institutions such as the Council of the European Union and the European Parliament allow for a transnational debate concerning the distribution of the burdens of the common good. Furthermore, the institutional architecture of the EU polity comprises a supranational court which offers legal protection to the fundamental rights of the nearly 450 million individuals who live across the EU. As I shall claim, this form of regional integration facilitates the pursuit of the common good at the global level.

Towards a global common good

As I have argued, most states in the current international system share at least a limited set of public values. This common set allows for a common moral standpoint from which they regard certain conditions and goals as desirable – the standpoint of the global common good. Why, then, do they often fail to address challenges such as climate change and global inequality? What seems to be currently missing is not a moral consensus around the undesirable nature of these outcomes but the appropriate institutional setting and incentive structure to address them.111 This gap has increased since nationalism has become “more prevalent in global politics in recent years”.112 Indeed, we seem to be facing a collective action problem: while at the normative level, most states agree that they should take more decisive action regarding these and other common challenges, they are usually unable to build the coalitions and mobilise the economic resources needed to address them. At the same time, even the most progressive democracies have resisted applying their high standards of respect for fundamental rights beyond their citizenries. Consider, for instance, the inhumane conditions of the Guantanamo prison and a few asylum centres in the EU member states.113 As I will claim in Chapter 3, this mismatch between the endorsement of common values and the lack of means to realise them suggests that a more consistent pursuit of the common good will imply institutional reforms at the supranational level.

It will be a central contention of the following chapters that the most effective strategy to promote the common good beyond borders is upscaling the ongoing processes of regional integration. Regional organisations such as the EU, ASEAN and the Mercosur facilitate moral convergence, policy coordination and burden-sharing. Indeed, their institutional frameworks host regular political and technical dialogues through which shared understandings of the common good can be developed and put into practice. To the extent regional integration brings about repeated interactions between states, it creates sizeable incentives for taking one another’s interests seriously.114 Since membership in these organisations presupposes state neighbourhood, they are particularly well positioned to address challenges with a strong regional dimension, such as mobility of people, water management and energy supply. Furthermore, regional organisations tend to develop schemes of cooperation based on reciprocity, such as free trade and free movement areas, which typically comprise the recognition and enforcement of at least a few fundamental rights of foreign citizens. Crucially, regional organisations play an important role as aggregators of preferences. This role is critical for the pursuit of the global common good since it is easier to negotiate compromises among a few regional players than among the nearly 200 world states.

The strategy to advance the global common good through regional integration underpinning this book takes the status quo as a starting point but stresses two critical domains for improvement.115 First, the competences of the existing regional organisations need to be updated and expanded in the face of the multiple challenges raised by globalisation. While comprehensive institutional frameworks already exist at the regional level, these frameworks possess limited means to deal with current challenges such as international tax evasion, water scarcity, social dumping and cyberterrorism.116 Indeed, the scope of regulatory and enforcement mechanisms required to address these problems effectively is clearly higher than the status quo. Second, the functioning of regional institutions needs to be strongly geared towards the common good. In other words, these institutions should not be held hostage to the struggle of national interests. As we will see in Chapters 3 and 4, this objective could be achieved by (partially) emancipating regions from national governments – that is, by democratising them and creating direct links to citizens – and increasing their capacity to respond to global challenges. This change would legitimise regional organisations to become the main actors in key global frameworks such as the United Nations, thus facilitating the pursuit of the global common good.117

Nevertheless, the strategy of advancing the global common good through regional associations will need to be complemented by an upgrade of the global institutional framework. In fact, many states do not belong to any regional block, and some regional associations are too loose or too weak to significantly advance the common good. Accordingly, strengthening the mandate and resources of global institutions such as the United Nations, the World Bank and the World Trade Organisation is key to effectively address many of the challenges mentioned above.118 Reforming these institutions would certainly not be an easy task, but it could be achieved if citizens increasingly pressed their governments to act upon such challenges.119 Indeed, as I will claim in Chapter 5, the prospects of ambitious reforms of the global framework depend ultimately on a genuine concern for the global common good by the citizens and their willingness to act upon it. In this regard, regional integration may teach us important lessons on how transnational bonds can be strengthened, which could then be replicated at the global level. Hence, acting at both regional and global levels will be required to advance the common good.

Conclusion

I have argued that the common good is a useful concept for contemporary political theory whenever equated with the public values of a given political community. Public values are enshrined in the fundamental laws of a polity, notably constitutions and international agreements, and are interpreted by public debates, policymaking practices and judicial decisions. I have claimed that public values offer a common moral standpoint from which relevant collective choices can be made despite moral and cultural diversity. Public values need to be endorsed explicitly by the political institutions of a community; they are not equivalent to the values embedded in cultural practices and are not attached to a particular ethnic or religious group. Furthermore, I have claimed that there may be overlapping public values across borders, particularly between states that have concluded international agreements. I have argued that the international diversity of the conceptions of the common good should be respected, provided that the governments comply with the fundamental rights recognised in international law. Finally, I claimed that in a pluralist international system grounded on respect for fundamental rights, the chances of achieving the global common good could be maximised through regional integration.

Notes

1 Patrick Riordan, A Grammar of the Common Good: Speaking of Globalisation (London, 2008).
2 As I will claim, realising the common good of a group of individuals may require certain sacrifices by one or more of its members. Consider the cases in which the common good is achieved through certain risky professions, such as firefighters, nurses and police officers. For this reason, I refrain from equating the common good with equal benefits for all citizens. However, it should be noted that this assumption is not consensual. For example, John Rawls has defined the common good as “maintaining conditions and achieving objectives that are similarly to everyone’s advantage”. For the quote, see John Rawls, A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition (Cambridge MA, 1999), p. 205. For a detailed discussion about the role of the common good in the works of John Rawls, see Roberto Luppi (ed.), John Rawls and the Common Good (New York, 2021).
3 See Charles Taylor, “Irreducibly Social Goods”, Philosophical Arguments (Cambridge MA, 1997).
4 George Duke, “The Distinctive Common Good”, The Review of Politics 78 (2016), pp. 227250.
5 This claim has forcefully been made by the so-called “responsive communitarians”, who attempt to balance the pursuit of the common good with the protection of certain key individual rights. See notably Amitai Etzioni, The Common Good (Cambridge, 2007).
6 For an influential formulation of this argument, see Kate Pickett and Richard Wilkinson, The Spirit Level: Why More Equal Societies Almost Always Do Better (New York, 2009). I shall discuss this issue in depth in Chapter 5.
7 Peter Singer, “Famine, Affluence and Morality”, Philosophy & Public Affairs 1 (1972), pp. 229243. The criticism that redistribution jeopardises individual rights has notably been put forward by Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (Malden, 1974).
8 Gross violations of fundamental rights are a reasonable proxy for impermissible harm because they cover particularly objectionable forms of behaviour that are jointly regarded as impermissible by rival moral accounts of harm. For instance, murder is morally wrong according to both deontological and utilitarian accounts of harm.
9 Contractarian accounts share the fundamental insight that political obligation is best understood in terms of a voluntary agreement concluded between a group of individuals with the purpose of ensuring that life in organised society is both possible and desirable. However, contractarian approaches diverge regarding the nature of the consent to the common rules. For an overview, see Ann Cudd and Seena Eftekhari, “Contractarianism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2021 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/contractarianism/ (accessed 15 February 2024).
10 Rawls, A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition, p. 205.
11 See, for instance, Justin Greenwood, Interest Representation in the European Union (London, 2017); and Christine Mahoney, Brussels versus the Beltway: Advocacy in the United States and the European Union (Washington, 2008)
12 For a similar conclusion, see Michael J. Sandel, The Tyranny of Merit: What’s Become of the Common Good? (London, 2021); and Robert B. Reich, The Common Good (New York, 2018).
13 See Aristotle, Politics, ed. R.F. Stalley (Oxford, 2009); and Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract, ed. Christopher Betts (Oxford, 1999).
14 See Aquinas, Political Writings, ed. R.W. Dyson (Cambridge, 2002). For a helpful discussion of Aquinas’ account of the common good, see Mary M. Keys, Aquinas, Aristotle, and the Promise of the Common Good (Cambridge, 2008)
15 See, for example, Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice: A Defence of Pluralism and Equality (New York, 1983); Charles Taylor, “Atomism”, in Shlomo Avineri and Avner de-Shalit (eds), Communitarianism and Individualism (Oxford, 1992); Amitai Etzioni, The Common Good (Cambridge, 2007).
16 For instance, the authors of a classic work within the communitarian movement have claimed that a “real community” is a community of memory and tradition. According to them, “the stories that make up a tradition contain conceptions of character, of what a good person is like, and of the virtues that define such character”. See Robert N. Bellah, Richard Madsen, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swidler and Steven M. Tipton, Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life (Berkeley, 1985), p. 153.
17 For example, in his influential discussion of what the United States should do to protect the public interest from powerful interest groups, Amitai Etzioni strikingly fails to consider the effects of globalisation. See Amitai Etzioni, The Spirit of Community (New York, 1993).
18 As discussed in the introduction, it is striking that communitarian authors have neglected the emergence of the EU polity. It bears noting that ongoing processes of regional integration pose a serious challenge to their case.
19 Melissa Schwartzberg, “Epistemic Democracy and Its ChallengesAnnual Review of Political Science 18 (2015), p. 187.
20 See Joshua Cohen, “An Epistemic Conception of Democracy”, Ethics 97 (1986), pp. 2638.
21 This applies not only to decision-makers and citizens, but also to policy experts. See Philip E. Tetlock, Expert Political Judgment: How Good Is It? How Can We Know? (Princeton, 2017).
22 On this point, see, for example, Douglas Murray, The Madness of Crowds: Gender, Race and Identity (London, 2019).
23 Schwartzberg, “Epistemic Democracy and Its Challenges”, p. 187.
24 This claim is key for the contractarian approach presented above. For an influential contemporary statement, see David Gauthier, Morals by Agreement (Oxford, 1987).
25 See W.B. Gallie, “Essentially Contested Concepts”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56 (1956), pp. 167198.
26 Accordingly, by employing expressions such as “pursuing the common good”, “realising the common good” and “advancing the common good” in this book I mean, respectively, pursuing, realising, and advancing the conception of the common good of a given polity, be it a national or a supranational polity, such as the EU. In other words, I do not assume that there is a single or objective understanding of the common good.
27 John Rawls, “The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus”, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 7 (1987), pp. 125.
28 William Rehg, “Solidarity and the Common Good: An Analytic Framework”, Journal of Social Philosophy 38 (2007), p. 7.
29 These two complementary tasks have been referred to as the “substantive” and the “procedural” dimensions of the common good. See Christopher Thomas, “Globalising Sovereignty? Pettit’s Neo-Republicanism, International Law, and International Institutions”, The Cambridge Law Journal 74 (2015), pp. 568591.
30 For instance, the so-called deliberative accounts of democracy have made several valuable proposals for new decision-making methods involving citizens. A key insight behind this approach is that, if citizens are well-informed and deliberate through appropriate channels, they are likely to make good collective choices. However, this approach has neglected the question of how to make representative institutions, which are subject to electoral incentives, more oriented towards the common good. As we shall see, this question is crucial for the EU institutional apparatus. For an overview of the “deliberative turn”, see Ian O’Flynn, Deliberative Democracy (Medford MA, 2022).
31 Adapted from François Foret and Oriane Calligaro, “Analysing European Values”, in European Values: Challenges and Opportunities for EU Governance (New York, 2018), pp. 34. Note that Foret and Calligaro also emphasise the role of values as cultural representations, which, as I will claim in the next section, should be distinguished from their role as moral guidelines for public life.
32 The preliminary question of why citizens are morally required to comply with the fundamental laws endorsed by political institutions is directly linked to the problem of political obligation, which I cannot discuss here. In what follows, I assume that citizens have certain associative obligations by virtue of their membership of a given political community, which include the duty to comply with the law. For a discussion, see Samuel Scheffler, “Membership and Political Obligation”, Journal of Political Philosophy 26 (2018), pp. 323.
33 The claim that the values endorsed via international agreements and conventions are a constitutive part of the conception of public morality of a given polity is the reason that leads me to rely on the concept of public values, instead of the narrower notion of constitutional values. Note that, in the context of EU membership the principle of the supremacy of EU law establishes that it has precedence over national law. This means that all national policies and legislation should be consistent not only with the constitutional values of member states, but also with EU values. For a discussion on the concept of constitutional values, see Gary Jeffrey Jacobsohn, “Constitutional Values and Principles”, in Michel Rosenfeld and András Sajó (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Comparative Constitutional Law (Oxford, 2012).
34 Barry Bozeman, Public Values and Public Interest: Counterbalancing Economic Individualism (Washington, 2007), p. 13.
35 In the field of legal theory, the point that fundamental laws express the standpoint of the common good has recently been made by Adrian Vermeule, Common Good Constitutionalism: Recovering the Classic Legal Tradition (Cambridge, 2022).
36 Note that, unlike most accounts of the common good, which focus on certain socially relevant choices, comprehensive doctrines of the good provide moral prescriptions that cover potentially every domain of life. For instance, utilitarianism considers that utility is intrinsically good and should always be maximised. For a classical statement, see John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, Utilitarianism and Other Essays, ed. Mark Philp (Oxford, 2015).
37 In certain cases, there may be strong tensions between the religious beliefs of some citizens, on the one hand, and the public values endorsed by the political institutions, on the other. Consider, for example, the current cleavages in the United States regarding the application of the value of freedom of choice to abortion. While, as I claim below, citizens are allowed to call for changes in the public values of their societies, they are required to comply with the existing set of public values without cherry-picking based on their beliefs. For a discussion, see Kent Greenawalt, Private Consciences and Public Reasons (Oxford, 1995).
38 My account has an affinity with the doctrine of constitutional patriotism, which “designates the idea that political attachment ought to centre on the norms, the values, and, more indirectly, the procedures of a liberal democratic constitution”. In Chapter 5, I will address the criticism raised recurrently against constitutional patriotism according to which, in the absence of certain common sociological features, such as culture and ethnicity, an attachment by citizens to an abstract set of values will be difficult to obtain. See Jan-Werner Müller and Kim Lane Scheppele, “Constitutional Patriotism: An Introduction”, International Journal of Constitutional Law 6 (2008), pp. 6771.
39 See Domingo Lovera-Parmo, “Protests, Riots, Inequality and a New Constitution for Chile”, Oxford Human Rights Hub (15 December 2019), https://ohrh.law. ox.ac.uk/protests-riots-inequality-and-a-new-constitution-for-chile/ (accessed 14 December 2022).
40 Constitution of the People’s Republic of China, article 4.
41 United Nations, “Gender Equality: Women and the Sustainable Development Goals”, www.un.org/en/global-issues/gender-equality (accessed 14 December 2022).
42 This methodology is typically applied by studies in the field of comparative constitutional law. For an overview of the available approaches in this discipline, see Oliver Brand, “Conceptual Comparisons: Towards a Coherent Methodology of Comparative Legal Studies”, Brooklyn Journal of International Law 32 (2007), pp. 405466. Note that the alternative – relying on empirical sources regarding the values of individuals, such as the World Values Survey – points us towards personal values, rather than public ones. See World Values Survey, www.worldvaluessurvey.org/wvs.jsp (accessed 26 July 2023).
43 Note that moral realism asserts the existence of certain moral facts. For an influential statement, see Thomas Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge MA, 1998).
44 On this point, see Uday Singh Mehta, Liberalism and Empire: A Study in Nineteenth-Century British Liberal Thought (Chicago, 1999).
45 Tom Ginsburg and Alberto Simpser (eds), Constitutions in Authoritarian Regimes (Cambridge, 2013).
46 See Constituição Política da República Portuguesa (1933), article 8. This phenomenon has been labelled “constitutions without constitutionalism”. See, for instance, Augusto Zimmermann, “Constitutions without Constitutionalism: The Failure of Constitutionalism in Brazil”, in Mortimer Sellers and Tadeusz Tomaszewski (eds), The Rule of Law in Comparative Perspective (Dordrecht, 2010).
47 This is often ensured through dedicated bodies that enforce the constitution and its values, such as the Federal Constitutional Court of Germany, the Constitutional Council of France, and the Supreme Court of the United States.
48 See, respectively, David Held, Models of Democracy (Cambridge, 2006) and Gøsta Esping-Anderson, The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism (Cambridge, 2004).
49 Consider, for instance, the European Social Charter (1961, revised in 1996); the European Commission’s White Paper on Social Policy (1994); the Directive 2004/38/EC (also known as the “Citizens Rights Directive”), the European Pillar of Social Rights (2017); the European Pillar of Social Rights Action Plan (2021); and landmark decisions by the Court of Justice of the European Union (CJEU), such as Elisabeta Dano and Florin Dano v. Jobcenter Leipzig.
50 A number of legal theorists have argued that legal orders that do not possess a codified constitution may nonetheless be grounded on a set of fundamental principles and values that guide the actions of public authorities and social relations. Even if these normative commitments have not been consolidated in a single document, they deserve the status of “constitutional order”. For a discussion regarding the paradigmatic case of the United Kingdom, see Colin Turpin and Adam Tomkins, British Government and the Constitution (Cambridge, 2007).
51 Kwame Anthony Appiah, The Honor Code: How Moral Revolutions Happen (New York, 2010).
52 For the so-called theory of “constitutional momentums”, which explains how constitutional change can happen without formally changing the constitution, see Bruce Ackerman’s, We the People, Volume 2: Transformations (Cambridge MA, 2000).
53 The Constitution of the United States, 1st to 27th amendments.
54 See, for instance, Serge Berstein, The Republic of de Gaulle 1958–1969 (Cambridge, 2006).
55 Emmanuel Macron, Discours du Président de la République lors de la Commémoration du Centenaire de L’Armistice (11 November 2018), www.elysee.fr/emmanuel-macron/2018/11/12/discours-du-president-de-la-republi que-emmanuel-macron-a-la-ceremonie-internationale-du-centenaire-de-larmist ice-du-11-novembre-1918-a-larc-de-triomphe (accessed 5 October 2022).
56 Shaun Walker, “Orbán Deploys Christianity with a Twist to Tighten Grip in HungaryThe Guardian (14 July 2019), www.theguardian.com/world/2019/jul/14/viktor-orban-budapest-hungary-christianity-with-a-twist (accessed 21 September 2022). Note that most Christian confessions endorse the values of tolerance and solidarity, particularly towards those most vulnerable, namely refugees.
57 Reuters, “Marine Le Pen Blames Radical Islamism for Charlie Hebdo Attack – Video”, The Guardian (8 January 2015), www.theguardian.com/world/video/2015/jan/08/marine-le-pen-radical-islamism-charlie-hebdo-attack-video (accessed 21 September 2022).
58 TellMAMA: Measuring Anti-Muslim Attacks, “Anti-Muslim Incidents in France after the Charlie Hebdo Massacre”, https://tellmamauk.org/project/anti-muslim-incidents-in-france-after-the-charlie-hebdo-massacre/ (accessed 26 July 2023).
59 See Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism (London, 2016).
60 This raises the question of whether a civic identity presupposes some degree of cultural homogeneity. This seems to be the case only to a limited extent. For instance, to allow for a meaningful public debate and to be able to exercise their rights, citizens should be able to speak a common language. Yet the existence of, say, a common ethnicity, religion and food habits do not seem to be necessary conditions to develop a shared civic identity.
61 Conrad Hackett, “5 Facts about the Muslim Population in Europe”, Pew Research Center (29 November 2017), www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2017/11/29/5- facts-about-the-muslim-population-in-europe/ (accessed 22 September 2022).
62 Samuel P. Huntington, The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World Order (London, 2002).
63 United Nations, “Treaty on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons”, www.un.org/disarmament/wmd/nuclear/npt/ (accessed 22 September 2022). The figures in this paragraph refer to ratification and accession, rather than the mere signature of international agreements as the former express unequivocally the endorsement of the agreements at stake.
64 It could be argued that the values enshrined in international treaties (such as peace, security, and cooperation) are “empty signifiers” (in the sense coined by Ernesto Laclau) that do not commit states to anything in practice. Accordingly, so the argument will go, they cannot be regarded as indicators of a transnational moral agreement. See Ernesto Laclau, On Populist Reason (London, 2005). However, as I have suggested above, the fact that abstract values (such as peace, security, and cooperation) must be interpreted by shared international bodies (such as the regular review conferences of the parties to the Treaty on the Non-Proliferation of Nuclear Weapons) to be translated into concrete policy actions does not mean that they are irrelevant. This is corroborated by the empirical finding that compliance with international agreements is “relatively good in general”. See George W. Downs and Michael A. Jones, “Reputation, Compliance, and International Law”, Journal of Legal Studies 31 (2002), p. S96.
65 For the figures, see Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, “Status of Ratification Interactive Dashboard”, https://indicators.ohchr.org/ (accessed 22 September 2022).
66 Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, “Status of Ratification Interactive Dashboard”.
67 Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, Selected Decisions of the Committee on the Elimination of Racial Discrimination (Geneva, 2012).
68 See, for instance, Mark G. Rolls, “Like-Minded States: New Zealand–ASEAN Relations in the Changing Asia-Pacific Strategic Environment”, in Anne-Marie Brady (ed.), Small States and the Changing Global Order: New Zealand faces the Future (Cham, 2019).
69 Riordan, A Grammar of the Common Good: Speaking of Globalization.
70 See James D. Fry, Bryane Michael and Natasha Pushkarna, The Values of International Organizations (Manchester, 2021).
71 Statute of the Council of Europe (1949).
72 Ian Manners, “The Constitutive Nature of Values, Images and Principles in the European Union”, in Sonia Lucarelli and Ian Manners (eds), Values and Principles in European Union Foreign Policy (New York, 2006).
73 ASEAN Charter, article 2.
74 Protocolo de Asunción sobre compromiso con la promoción y protección de los Derechos Humanos en el MERCOSUR and Protocolo de Ushuaia sobre Compromiso Democrático en el MERCOSUR, La Republica de Bolivia e la Republica de Chile.
75 This view is in tension with the cultural approach to European values. As I will argue in Chapter 2, the cultural approach is of limited interest for the questions addressed by this book.
76 Note that, as I have suggested, addressing the question “what does the common good of the EU mean?” presupposes the identification of a substantive source of a common standpoint within the EU polity (such as EU values). In the absence of such source, any account of the common good of the EU will suffer from a lack of specification.
77 Of course, some states may endorse a particular value but systematically fail to comply with it. More to the point, there may be no value that all world states have equally endorsed. However, these cases do not jeopardise the debate about the global common good. Indeed, it would be implausible to think that the concept of global common good is only useful if all world states endorsed a set of common values and complied with them. For example, if all states bar North Korea and Iran agreed that the non-proliferation of nuclear weapons was desirable, the abstention of these two should not prevent us from acknowledging a widely shared understanding of this good at the global level.
78 United Nations, “Status of the Paris Agreement”, https://treaties.un.org/Pages/ViewDetails.aspx?src=TREATY&mtdsg_no=XXVII-7-d&chapter=27&clang= _en#1 (accessed 23 September 2022). A similar point is made by A.C. Grayling, For the Good of the World: Is Global Agreement on Global Challenges Possible? (London, 2022), p. 180.
79 Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, “Status of Ratification Interactive Dashboard”.
80 Constitution of the Islamic Republic of Iran, article 1.
81 Ruhollah Khomeini, American Plots against Iran Speech (1979), http://emam.com/posts/view/15718/Speech (accessed 6 October 2022); George W. Bush, State of the Union Address (2002), https://georgewbush-whitehouse.archives.gov/news/releases/2002/01/20020129–11.html (accessed 6 October 2022).
82 For the normative conception of the community in Nazi Germany, see Martina Steber and Bernhard Gotto (eds), Visions of Community in Nazi Germany: Social Engineering and Private Lives (Oxford, 2014).
83 Anna Stilz, “The Value of Self-Determination”, in David Sobel, Peter Vallentyne and Steven Wall (eds), Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, volume 2 (Oxford, 2016), p. 98.
84 Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations (New York, 2015), p. 89.
85 See Stephen M. Walt, “Top 10 Warning Signs of Liberal Imperialism”, Foreign Policy (10 May 2013), https://foreignpolicy.com/2013/05/20/top-10-warning-signs-of-liberal-imperialism/ (accessed 30 September 2022).
86 Daniele Archibugi, The Global Commonwealth of Citizens: Toward Cosmopolitan Democracy (Princeton, 2008).
87 On this point, see Seyla Benhabib, Another Cosmopolitanism (Oxford, 2006).
88 Note that global moral progress does not necessarily presuppose the recognition of universal moral truths. For instance, according to the influential view of Peter Singer, moral progress takes place when the moral agents expand their circle of moral concern – that is, from family to friends to fellow citizens and to the individuals in the rest of the world. See Peter Singer, The Expanding Circle: Ethics and Sociobiology (New York, 1981).
89 This norm is notably enshrined in the United Nations Charter.
90 See Michael Walzer, “Governing the Globe: What Is the Best We Can Do?”, Dissent (Fall edition, 2000).
91 Bruce M. Russett and John D. Sullivan, “Collective Goods and International Organization”, International Organization 25 (1971).
92 Note that the US embargo has made the export of Cuban products more difficult and it lowered the degree of access to certain basic goods, such as food and medical supplies by its population. For an overview of the relations between the United States and Cuba, see Arne Westad, The Cold War: A World History (London, 2018).
93 Note that this focus on the rights presently codified in international law does not substitute for the existence of additional moral rights that have not yet been granted legal recognition. My goal here is to refer to standards that are widely accepted and can serve effectively as a reference point for all states. For a discussion on the need to expand the prevailing understanding of fundamental rights, see Charles Beitz and Robert Goodin (eds), Global Basic Rights (Oxford, 2011).
94 See, for instance, James Crawford, “The Criteria for Statehood in International Law”, British Yearbook of International Law 48 (1977), pp. 93182.
95 For instance, Hobbes claims that citizens have a moral right to run away from the authorities if they have been sentenced to death. See Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. Noel Malcolm. More generally, the right to self-preservation has played a key role in the structure of the arguments of most natural rights theories. For an overview, see Richard Tuck, Natural Rights Theories: Their Origin and Development (Cambridge, 1981).
96 Note that the duty to respect fundamental rights is justifiable on the grounds of most available moral theories, ranging from natural law theory to deontology to virtue ethics to moderate versions of utilitarianism.
97 Consider, for instance, the use of the so-called “smart sanctions” against ruling elites and trade of weapons. On this point, see Joy Gordon, “Smart Sanctions Revisited”, Ethics & International Affairs 25 (2011), pp. 315335.
98 John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge MA, 2001).
99 Note that this book focuses on the EU polity, where the track record of compliance with fundamental rights is generally high. The recent cases of gross and systemic violations of EU values in a limited number of member states will be discussed in detail in Chapter 2.
100 Consider, for instance, the following sources: the Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide (1948); the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966); the Convention on the Rights of the Child (1989); the International Convention on the Suppression and Punishment of the Crime of Apartheid (1973); the International Convention for the Protection of All Persons from Enforced Disappearance (2006); the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (2006).
101 This question has been a matter of an extensive debate in the specialised literature and cannot be addressed here. See, for instance, Henry Shue, Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy (Princeton, 1996); and Joshua Cohen, “Is there a Human Right to Democracy?”, in Christine Sypnowich (ed.), The Egalitarian Conscience: Essays in Honour of G. A. Cohen (Oxford, 2006).
102 This is the reason why I abstain from directly equating fundamental rights with a comprehensive list of human rights. Indeed, the contemporary human rights regime has been criticised on the grounds of being “Eurocentric in character and hegemonic in practice”. See Hakimeh Saghaye-Biria, “Decolonizing the ‘Universal’ Human Rights Regime: Questioning American Exceptionalism and Orientalism”, ReOrient 4 (2018), pp. 5977. However, it should be noted the fact that the history of human rights has been Eurocentric does not mean that the idea of global human rights is unsound. For this view, see Fernando Suárez Müller, “Eurocentrism, Human Rights, and Humanism”, International Journal of Applied Philosophy 26 (2012), pp. 279293.
103 Indeed, it would be implausible to think that occasional violations of the fundamental rights of some individuals would justify interference. Even states deeply committed to respecting fundamental rights cannot ensure compliance levels of 100%. For instance, the public authorities of France and the Netherlands have occasionally been condemned by the CJEU and the European Court of Human Rights for infractions against some of their citizens.
104 In the domestic sphere, the tension between the enhancement of the common good and of individual rights has generated an intense debate opposing communitarian to liberal scholars. For an overview, see Daniel Bell, Communitarianism and its Critics (Oxford, 1993).
105 Robert Rapier, “The World’s Top Lithium Producers”, Forbes (13 December 2020), www.forbes.com/sites/rrapier/2020/12/13/the-worlds-top-lithium-produc ers/ (accessed 2 August 2023).
106 On the role of lithium in the green transition, see, for instance, World Bank, Minerals for Climate Action: The Mineral Intensity of the Clean Energy Transition (Washington, 2020).
107 Of course, there may be additional grounds to share natural resources, notably related to justice claims. For a discussion, see Leif Wenar, “Natural Resources”, in David Held and Pietro Maffettone (eds), Global Political Theory (Cambridge, 2016).
108 The question of whether a given sacrifice is proportional should be assessed in light of the necessity and the magnitude of the sacrifice at stake vis-à-vis the goal to be achieved. For a comprehensive discussion, see Aharon Barak, Proportionality: Constitutional Rights and their Limitations (Cambridge, 2012).
109 On this point, see Seyla Benhabib, The Rights of Others: Aliens, Residents and Citizens (Cambridge, 2004).
110 See, for instance, Joseph H. Chung, “Human Rights Violations by Multinational Corporations: Corruption, Lawlessness and the ‘Global Value Chain’”, Centre for Research on Globalisation, www.globalresearch.ca/human-rights-violat ion-multinational-corporations-global-value-chain-corruption-lawlessness/5779160 (accessed 26 July 2023).
111 The need for a more comprehensive institutional framework at the supranational level has been advocated by several authors, notably Jürgen Habermas, The Postnational Constellation: Political Essays (Cambridge, 2001).
112 Florian Bieber, “Is Nationalism on the Rise? Assessing Global Trends”, Ethnopolitics 17 (2018), p. 519.
113 See, for instance, Human Rights Watch, Locked Up Alone: Detention Conditions and Mental Health at Guantanamo (New York, 2008); and Anthony Deutsch, “Dutch Refugee Council Sues State over ‘Inhumane’ Asylum Centres”, Reuters (18 August 2022), www.reuters.com/world/europe/dutch-refugee-council-sues-state-over-inhumane-asylum-centres-2022-08-18/ (accessed 1 January 2023).
114 See, for instance, Stephen J. Majeski, “Generating and Maintaining Cooperation in International Relations: A Model of Repeated Interaction Among Groups in Complex and Uncertain Situations”, International Interactions 21 (1996), pp. 265289.
115 This is line with the so-called practice-dependence approach in the fields of moral and political theory. As I mentioned in the introduction, the main reasons to prefer this approach are that it offers clear practical guidance and it has better feasibility prospects than idealistic approaches that would attempt to redesign the international system from scratch. For a discussion, see Eva Erman and Niklas Möller, “What Distinguishes the Practice-Dependent Approach to Justice?”, Philosophy & Social Criticism 42 (2016), pp. 323.
116 In addition to already mentioned cases such as the EU, ASEAN, Mercosur and the African Union, consider the Economic Community of West African States, the Gulf Cooperation Council, the European Free Trade Association and the Nordic Council.
117 Note that this already applies to the EU to a certain extent. For instance, the EU has competence to negotiate and conclude international agreements in certain areas on behalf of its member states, such as customs. See Council of the European Union, “The Role of the Council in International Agreements”, www.consilium.europa.eu/en/council-eu/international-agreements/ (accessed 25 October 2022).
118 A number of valuable proposals to improve the problem-solving capacity of these institutions are currently available in the literature. See, for example, Jussi M. Hanhimäki, “Reform and Challenges: the Future of the United Nations”, The United Nations: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford, 2008); Pedro Alba, Patricia Bliss-Guest and Laura Tuck, “Reforming the World Bank to Play a Critical Role in Addressing Climate Change”, Center for Global Development Policy Paper 288 (2023); Marianne Schneider-Petsinger, Reforming the World Trade Organization: Prospects for Transatlantic Cooperation and the Global Trade System (2020).
119 Philip Kotler, Advancing the Common Good: Strategies for Businesses, Governments and Nonprofits (Santa Barbara, 2019), p. 93.
  • Collapse
  • Expand

All of MUP's digital content including Open Access books and journals is now available on manchesterhive.

 

Beyond Nationalism

Acting and thinking for the common good in the European Union

Metrics

All Time Past Year Past 30 Days
Abstract Views 0 0 0
Full Text Views 229 229 25
PDF Downloads 3 3 0